Approaching Philosophy of Religion by Anthony C. Thiselton
Author:Anthony C. Thiselton
Language: eng
Format: epub
ISBN: 9780281076772
Publisher: SPCK
Published: 2017-04-07T16:00:00+00:00
2 Subjective and utilitarian views of the good: Hobbes, Hume and Bentham
In the early modern era, Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679) tended to define good merely as what was pleasant, expedient or useful, and human beings as, basically, egoists. Desires and aversions were virtually physical dictates. Many have described his ethics as no more than psychological hedonism. In Leviathan he described Aristotle’s system as absurd, and even repugnant to government. Indeed Hobbes could see, in the end, only the monarch’s use of force as a way of maintaining order and a semblance of ‘good’ for society. Power, he said, is the chief regulating principle in ethical judgement. ‘Virtue’ is any esteemed quality that sets people above their fellows. Love is valuable only as a social influence. Benevolence is merely ‘a half-conscious mutual contract’ of expectation of a good return for favours done. Everyone is ‘vehemently in love with their own opinions’.162
David Hume (1711–76) stressed consequential ethics, like Hobbes, but in a more utilitarian way. His method was naturalistic and dependent on observation. Unlike the Aristotelian-Thomist tradition he believed that reason was the slave of the passions. Good is the action ‘of whose consequences most men approve’ and what is ‘fitted to be beneficial to society’.163 We cannot infer ‘ought’ from descriptions of what ‘is’ (although some dispute this interpretation).164 Although he is, like Hobbes, naturalistic, Hume modifies Hobbes by utilitarian concerns.
Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) more explicitly advocated utilitarianism as seeking ‘the greatest happiness of the greatest number’.165 His criterion of ethics is whether something tends to augment or diminish this. He even attempted to measure happiness by ‘intensity, duration and extent’. Clearly, as in Hume, his ethics are consequential; i.e. he asks, ‘What are the consequences of this action?’ One problem is that of measurement. How does extreme pleasure for a handful of individuals rank against the low-level pleasure of the very many? In his politics, Bentham’s criterion is ‘the mass of the interests of individuals’. Incidentally he rejected all notions of ‘natural rights’.
J. S. Mill (1806–73) built on Bentham’s utilitarian ethics. He attempted to address the problem of criteria and measurement by distinguishing between ‘lower’ and ‘higher’ pleasures. One of his best-known ethical axioms is, ‘It is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig satisfied’.166 But to introduce qualitative difference between pleasures is to add another ethical criterion to utilitarianism. He regarded utility as the ultimate appeal on all ethical questions.
Download
This site does not store any files on its server. We only index and link to content provided by other sites. Please contact the content providers to delete copyright contents if any and email us, we'll remove relevant links or contents immediately.
The Lost Art of Listening by Michael P. Nichols(7160)
Why I Am Not A Calvinist by Dr. Peter S. Ruckman(4045)
The Rosicrucians by Christopher McIntosh(3371)
Wicca: a guide for the solitary practitioner by Scott Cunningham(3040)
Signature in the Cell: DNA and the Evidence for Intelligent Design by Stephen C. Meyer(2875)
Real Sex by Lauren F. Winner(2861)
The Holy Spirit by Billy Graham(2775)
To Light a Sacred Flame by Silver RavenWolf(2674)
The End of Faith by Sam Harris(2631)
The Gnostic Gospels by Pagels Elaine(2393)
Waking Up by Sam Harris(2330)
Nine Parts of Desire by Geraldine Brooks(2279)
Jesus by Paul Johnson(2224)
Devil, The by Almond Philip C(2204)
The God delusion by Richard Dawkins(2186)
Heavens on Earth by Michael Shermer(2186)
Kundalini by Gopi Krishna(2089)
Chosen by God by R. C. Sproul(2053)
The Nature of Consciousness by Rupert Spira(1980)
